Science of writing
In this series on Jack Derrida’s Of Grammatology, we further examine
Derrida’s thesis under the chapter ‘Linguistic and Grammatology’. In
this chapter Derrida describes the relationship between linguistic and
Grammatology.
Derrida builds up his thesis; “ The science of linguistics determines
language—its field of objectivity—in the last instance and in the
irreducible simplicity of its essence, as the unity of the phone, the
glossa, and the logos. This determination is by rights anterior to all
the eventual differentiations that could arise within the systems of
terminology of the different schools (language/speech [langue/parole];
code/message; scheme/usage; linguistic/logic;
phonology/phonematics/phonetics/glossematics).
And even if one wished to keep sonority on the side of the sensible
and contingent signifier (which would be strictly speaking impossible,
since formal identities isolated within a sensible mass are already
idealities that are not purely sensible), it would have to be admitted
that the immediate and privileged unity which founds significance and
the acts of language is the articulated unity of sound and sense within
the phonie. With regard to this unity, writing would always be
derivative, accidental, particular, exterior, doubling the signifier:
phonetic. “Sign of a sign,” said Aristotle, Rousseau, and Hegel.
|
Jacques Derrida |
Yet, the intention that institutes general linguistics as a science
remains in this respect within a contradiction. Its declared purpose
indeed confirms, saying what goes without saying, the subordination of
grammatology, the historico-metaphysical reduction of writing to the
rank of an instrument enslaved to a full and originarily spoken
language. But another gesture (not another statement of purpose, for
here what does not go without saying is done without being said, written
without being uttered) liberates the future of a general grammatology of
which linguistics-phonology would be only a dependent and circumscribed
area. Let us follow this tension between gesture and statement in
Saussure. ”
Derrida develops his thesis citing Saussure. He observes, “ On the
one hand, true to the Western tradition that controls not only in theory
but in practice (in the principle of its practice) the relationships
between speech and writing, Saussure does not recognize in the latter
more than a narrow and derivative function. Narrow because it is nothing
but one modality among others, a modality of the events which can befall
a language whose essence, as the facts seem to show, can remain forever
un-contaminated by writing.
Oral tradition
“Language does have an ... oral tradition that is independent of
writing” (Cours de linguistique générale, p. 46). Derivative because
representative: signifier of the first signifier, representation of the
self-present voice, of the immediate, natural, and direct signification
of the meaning (of the signified, of the concept, of the ideal object or
what have you).
Saussure takes up the traditional definition of writing which,
already in Plato and Aristotle, was restricted to the model of phonetic
script and the language of words. Let us recall the Aristotelian
definition: “Spoken words are the symbols of mental experience and
written words are the symbols of spoken words.” Saussure: “Language and
writing are two distinct systems of signs; the second exists for the
sole purpose of representing the first” (p. 45; italics added) [p. 23
**]. This representative determination, beside communicating without a
doubt essentially with the idea of the sign, does not translate a choice
or an evaluation, does not betray a psycho-logical or metaphysical
presupposition peculiar to Saussure; it describes or rather reflects the
structure of a certain type of writing: phonetic writing, which we use
and within whose element the epistémè in general (science and
philosophy), and linguistics in particular, could be founded.
One should, moreover, say model rather than structure; it is not a
question of a system constructed and functioning perfectly, but of an
ideal explicitly directing a functioning which in fact is never
completely phonetic. In fact, but also for reasons of essence to which I
shall frequently return.
To be sure this factum of phonetic writing is massive; it commands
our entire culture and our entire science, and it is certainly not just
one fact among others. Nevertheless it does not respond to any necessity
of an absolute and universal essence. Using this as a point of
departure, Saussure defines the project and object of general
linguistics: “The linguistic object is not defined by the combination of
the written word and the spoken word: the spoken form alone constitutes
the object”
According to Saussure, word is ‘Now the word (vox) is already a unity
of sense and sound, of concept and voice, or, to speak a more rigorously
Saussurian language, of the signified and the signifier.’
Derrida observes, “This last terminology was moreover first proposed
in the domain of spoken language alone, of linguistics in the narrow
sense and not in the domain of semiology (“I propose to retain the word
sign [signe] to designate the whole and to replace concept and
sound-image respectively by signified and signifier. The word is thus
already a constituted unity, an effect of “the somewhat mysterious fact
. . . that ‘thought sound’ implies divisions”. Even if the word is in
its turn articulated, even if it implies other divisions, as long as one
poses the question of the relationships between speech and writing in
the light of the indivisible units of the “thought-sound,” there will
always be the ready response. Writing will be “phonetic,” it will be the
outside, the exterior representation of language and of this
“thought-sound.”
It must necessarily operate from already constituted units of
signification, in the formation of which it has played no part. ”Potts
observes, “Two differences from Foucault. (a) Though both speak of
“epochs,” Foucault’s epochs are typically about 200 years long. Derrida
speaks of only one epoch, which spans Western history from the birth of
Greek philosophy to the present.
Derrida thus believes that what governs his epoch is something more
fundamental than the “epistemes” that govern Foucault’s. Whereas
Foucault constantly refers to the facts of other epochs in a way that
requires him to possess an extra-historical vantage point he denies to
the rest of us (a point amusingly exposed by Derrida in “Cogito and the
History of Madness”; e.g., “everything transpires as if Foucault knew
what ‘madness’ means”, Derrida refuses to step outside the confines of
our own epoch and emphasizes that deconstruction operates within and
upon the logocentric framework.”.
Potts also observes that Derrida’s argument is self-contradictory as
the notion of ‘purity’ is failed ‘because the pure presence of being is
inevitably distorted by the process of linguistic or conceptual
signification’. |