Literature and varieties of history
[Part 7]
In today’s column on the topic of literature and varieties of
history, I wish to focus on the work of the French thinker Michel
Foucault (1926- 1984). He was a philosopher, historian, social activist.
His is a remarkable career, and his intellectual odyssey carried him
across several fields of inquiry and frequently ended up in unmapped
territories. He is the author of such widely influential works as The
Archaeology of Knowledge, The Birth of the Clinic, Discipline and
Punish, The History of Sexuality.
There are many facets to his writings, and I would like to confine
myself to his significance as a historian. Foucault is generally
regarded as one of the most important French thinkers of the twentieth
century and some would argue that he was the most important French
thinker of the twentieth century.
His works have had a profound impact on both the humanities and
social sciences; he was able to open up new avenues of social inquiry
that have been profitably pursued by later scholars. He published a
number of scholarly books that served to transform our understanding of
the way various institutions function in Western cultures.
His book Madness and Civilization was devoted to an analysis of
modern mental institutions while The Birth of the Clinic focused on the
hospitals; In Discipline and Punish he explored the ways in which
prisons function as social institutions and his The History of Sexuality
he dealt with the institutions of family and schools. In all these
studies, one of Foucault’s primary concerns was to investigate into the
role of power in society.
He examined the notion of power in a way that marked a radical
departure from the standard approaches; he was keen to probe into the
pervasive and insidious mechanisms by which power ‘reaches into the very
gain of individuals, touches their bodies and inserts itself into their
actions and attitudes, their discourses, learning processes and everyday
lives.’
Michel Foucault, interestingly and contrary to conventional wisdom,
perceived of power not solely in negative terms; he also discussed its
positive and productive aspects. I shall discuss this aspect later in
the column. His explorations into medicine, madness, sexuality and
punishment were united by a vision that underscored the role of power
play in the management of truth, reason and knowledge.
Controversial
As I stated earlier Michel Foucault is one of the most influential
thinkers of the modern era. On numerous occasions, in my columns, I have
discussed various facets of his achievements. He was consequential as he
was controversial, widely appreciated as he was misunderstood, received
with boundless enthusiasm and fierce irritation. This is indeed the fate
of most innovative thinkers. Today, my primary interest is on his work
as a historian, and his writings on history, to my mind, have generated
some of the staunchest resistance from academics.
Before I examine this theme let me offer a quotation from the eminent
American anthropologist Clifford Geertz. It summarises admirably the
attainments and problems of Foucault as a contemporary thinker.
‘Michel Foucault erupted onto the intellectual scene at the beginning
of the sixties with his Histoire de la folie ( Madness and
Civilization), an unconventional but still reasonably recognizable
history of the western experience of madness.
He has become, in the years since, a kind of impossible object; a
non-historian historian, an anti-human human scientist, and a
counter-strucruralist structuralist. If we add to this his terse,
impacted style, which manages to be seen imperious and doubt-ridden at
the same time, and a method which supports sweeping summary with
eccentric detail, the resemblance of his work to an Escher drawing –
stairs rising to platforms lower than themselves, doors leading outside
that beings you back inside – is complete.’
It is interesting that Geertz should allude to the Dutch graphic
artist M.C. Escher. (1898-1972). He was greatly influenced by
mathematics and created works of art that were puzzling and cognitively
challenging. Geertz’s statement points to the antimonies and
contradictions that characterize Foucault’s work as well its complex
reception by the public. Foucault sought to introduce a new kind of
historical analysis that stood in sharp contrast to mainstream
historical investigations and thereby incurring the hostility of many of
the historians associate with the establishment.
As he once remarked, ‘is it not necessary to draw a line between
those who believe that we can continue to situate our present
discontinuities within the historical and transcendental traditions of
the nineteenth century and those who are making a great effort to
liberate themselves, once and for all, from this conceptual framework.’
Historian
Here, Foucault is underlining what to him, as a historian, is a very
significant point.
As a commentator on history, it was his declared intention to move
away from universalist, foundationalist, normative view points and
instead lay stress on concepts of difference, discontinuity and
contingency.
He was keen to dissolve such abstract essences and universal
categories as truth, reason, history, right, which mainstream historians
held in reverence, into multiplicities of distinct social and cultural
forms. In doing so, he was persuaded to question the disciplinary
boundaries that traditionally existed between history, philosophy,
psychology, political theory; he was also interested in abandoning the
conventional approaches to these disciplines.
As one scholar remarked, ‘he does not do theory in the modern sense,
which aims at clarity, consistency, comprehensiveness, objectivity and
truth. Rather, he offers fragments, fictions, truth-games, heterotopias,
tools, experiments that he hopes will prompt his readers to think and
act in new ways. Trying to blaze new intellectual and political trails,
Foucault abandons both liberalism and Marxism and seeks a new kind of
critical theory and politics.’
Foucault’s approach to history, then, is the very antithesis of
Hegel’s. Hegel proposed a vision of history that was marked by
continuity, progress, reconciliation, freedom.
Foucault’s concept of history was diametrically opposed to this. Like
the German philosopher Nietzsche, whom Foucault admired greatly, he
proposed a vision of history that rejected universality, inevitable
progress, the multiplication of ever growing conflicts, the prominence
of differences, and an emphasis on rupture and contingency.
This was, therefore, a whole new approach to the understanding and
writing of history. What is clearly evident in Foucault’s writings on
and in history is his disenchantment with enlightenment values such as
universalism and rationalism and optimism and humanism and instead focus
on discontinuities, sudden reversals, the salience of differences.
Another important shift that Foucault effectuated relates to the
question of the objects of scientific study. He displaced emphasis from
the ways in which scientific objects are constituted to the manner in
which human beings are made into subjects of knowledge to the extent
that they themselves are made into objects of knowledge. As Foucault
remarked, ‘while historians of science in France were interested
essentially in the problem of how a scientific object is constituted,
the question I asked myself was this; how is it that the human subject
took itself as the object of possible knowledge?
Through what forms of rationality, and historical conditions? And
finally at what price? This predilection is vitally connected to
Foucault’s ambition of providing a critique of the ways in which
populations in contemporary societies are controlled and disciplined by
sanctioning the claims to knowledge and the practices associated with
the human sciences. Hence his deep concern with such fields of inquiry
as psychiatry, psychology, medicine, sociology and criminology.
It is his conviction that human sciences have succeeded in
undercutting the classical social order premised on rights and
independence and have put in place new operations of power exercised
through disciplinary mechanisms. These concerns of Foucault are
interconnected and shape his vision of history and historiography.
Transformation
Foucault succeeded in bringing about a fundamental transformation in
our thinking about history. He challenged the standard approaches to
history and knowledge production by repudiating the empirical method
much favoured by historians and replaced with narrative interpretation
as the principal mode of historical knowing and explication. He was
adamant in his assertion there is no unmediated access to the past and
reality available to us, and therefore the only way in which we can
access the past is through language which is, of course, inseparably
linked to power and legitimacy.
Clearly, this is a mode of thinking, as Foucault himself admitted,
that was greatly influenced by Nietzsche. Foucault’s contention is that
we cannot know the past objectively, because this idea of objectivity
itself is a product of historical factors and cultural forces. This line
of thinking, it is apparent, went against the central tenets of
traditional history-making.
Many mainstream historians have characterised Foucault as an
anti-historian. This is primarily due to two reasons. On the one hand,
he is unwilling to privilege the notion much valorised by historians of
scientific truth, objectivity and standard forms of evidentially derived
investigations.
On the other hand, he rejects the easy linear chain of causation
favored by mainstream historians between events and periods, and instead
proposes a history that is marked by non-linearity and discontinuities
and sudden ruptures. In addition, Foucault believes that all
representations of the past are partial in both senses if the term.
This, once again, had a devastating impact on traditional
historiography.
Congruence
Another significant aspect of Foucault’s vision of history was that,
methodologically speaking, there is congruence between the writings of
philosophers of history and the work of historians. This has great
implications for the forward movement of historiography. What Foucault
was articulating was the need for historians to be self-reflective –
self-reflective about the content, about the style. It also raises
issues abut the nature of the production of historical knowledge and how
it is made use of.
As Alun Munslow observed, ’ultimately ,as he says, the past construed
as history is an endless process of interpretation by the historian as
an act of imagination, and our categories of analysis, assumptions,
models and figurative style all themselves become a part of the history
we are trying to unravel.’ What this underscores is the essential
self-reflexivity that characterizes the historian’s investigative
pursuits.
In order to understand Michel Foucault’s distinctive approach to
history we need to pay attention to an important distinction he made
between total history and general history. It was his belief that total
history should give way to general history. By total history what he
meant was a history that had the ability to draw diverse phenomena
toward a central and unifying center; ideas of principles, meanings,
visions, general understandings of culture, converged around a
recognisable center.
This same principle was discernible in practices related to
economics, politics, social life, religion and so on; they were subject
to a centripetal power, were pulled towards a center that went by the
general designation a period of time. In contrast, general history calls
attention to, ‘series, segmentations, limits, difference of level,
time-lags, anachronistic survivals, possible types of relation. ’What
the adherents of general history were interested in were not the
conjunctions of diverse histories such as economic, political, cultural,
or the quest for similarities and coincidences between them. Total
history focuses on cohesion and causality and while general history
rejects totality in favor of interplays and correlations. It was the
preferred function of the general historian to assess what kinds of
connections and linkages may be forged between them. Clearly, Foucault’s
interests were closely wrapped up with the concept of general history.
Objectives
If one were to examine Foucault’s corpus of writing very carefully
one would be struck by the fact that one of his central objectives as a
thinker and writer has to been to dethrone the human subject and the
accompanying consciousness and replace it with language, rhetoric,
cultural practices. This objective finds expression in his historical
writings as well. Two seminal thinks who sought to minimize the
centrality of human consciousness were Karl Marx and Friedrich
Nietzsche.
Marx was interested in displaying how human consciousness was shaped
by social forces while Nietzsche related human consciousness and
morality to social struggles and power plays. Both had the effect of
undermining human consciousness. Foucault, however, felt that their
attempts had been misinterpreted by later commentators. Marx was
presented as a historian of totalities while Nietzsche was made into a
philosopher who was interested in origins. Both these sets of
mischaracterisations, he contended, twisted the original intent of the
two thinkers.
Consequently, Foucault aimed to clarify as forcefully as he could the
issue of subjecthood and consciousness. This attempt of Foucault was
denounced by some historians as an attempt to undermine the very
foundations of history. Human consciousness is, according to traditional
thinking, what united the disparate historical events spread out over
time, and hence it was valued as a master concept. Foucault once
remarked that,’ The cry goes up that one is murdering history whenever
in a historical analysis- and especially if it is concerned with
thought, ideas of knowledge – one is seen to be using in too obvious a
way the categories of discontinuity and difference, the notions of
threshold, rupture, and transformation, the description of series and
limits.
One will be denounced for attacking the inalienable rights of history
and the very foundations of any possible historicity. But one must not
be deceived, what is being bewailed with such vehemence is not the
disappearance of history, but the eclipse of that form of history that
was secretly, but entirely related to the synthetic activity of the
subject….’
One area in which Michel Foucault’s ideas are especially relevant is
in the domain of intellectual history; his writings, by way of
challenges and interrogations, have much to offer to practitioners in
this domain. One can say that intellectual history, as it has developed
in the West, rests on four thought -pillars. The first it takes for
granted the unity of the Western intellectual tradition; second, it
recognizes a continuous and steady evolution of this tradition; third,
it is held that the values that support this tradition are reason and
freedom; fourth, it focuses in harmony and unity as opposed to conflicts
and fissures.
It is this intellectual tradition that Foucault sought to subvert as
evidenced in a book like the Archaeology of Knowledge. Understandably,
many historians opposed his efforts. Some accused him of coming up with
new analytical concepts such as discourse, archeology, episteme that ate
too abstract and fuzzy and unable to perform efficaciously the tasks if
historical investigation. It is the considered judgment of these
denigrators that Foucault has forsaken the field of inquiry called
history for a kind of structural analysis that is inadequate to the task
of examining social change.
Observation
Commenting on such criticisms, Foucault makes the observation that,
‘continuous history is the indispensable correlative of the founding
function of the subject; the guarantee that everything that has eluded
him may be restored to him; the certainty that time will disperse
nothing without restoring in a reconstituted unity; the promise that one
day the subject – in the form of historical consciousness – sill once
again be able to appropriate, to bring back under his sway, all those
things that are kept a distance by difference, and find them in what
might be called his abode.’
The kind of history that he wishes to promote is what he terms a form
of archeology. This archaeology, in his words, will be able to’ operate
a de-centering that leaves no privilege center.’ in his historical
writings it is his proclaimed desire to see ‘questions of human being,
consciousness, origin and the subject emerge, intersect, mingle and
separate off.’
In order to comprehend and map the trajectory of history-making that
Foucault has taken, we need to focus on two crucial technical terms –
archeology and genealogy. Clearly, he is deploying these two words in a
way that is different from the manner in which they are employed in
daily parlance. Let us first consider the term archaeology. This
metaphor tells us that the intention of Foucault us to excavate
knowledge, to search for underlying conditions of possibilities and
shaping factors. As an archaeologist of western societies, he is on a
quest to uncover the basic codes of discourse and knowledge as they take
shape and expand within a historical context. It is the aim of
archaeology to explore the rules that guide human thinking and
knowledge.
In Foucault’s own words, ‘the goal of archaeology is to; explore
scientific discourse not from the point of view of the individuals who
are speaking, nor from the point of view of the formal structures of
what they are saying, but from the point of view of the riles that come
into play in the very existence of such discourse…the historical
analysis of scientific discourse should, in the last resort, be subject
not to a theory of the knowing subject but rather to a theory of
discursive practice’ This term discursive practice occurs frequently in
Foucault’s writings as well as in those of his followers.
Levels
Foucault, then, it is clear, is seeking to undermine the individual
subject as the originator of discourse and demonstrate how it develops
inharmoniously at various levels without the aid of a unifying and
guiding consciousness of a subject. This is very different from
traditional history, As a perceptive expositor of Foucault’s writings,
Steven Best remarks, ‘archaeology seeks to identify the conditions of
possibility of knowledge, the rules of formation, of discourse
rationality (discursive objects, concepts, statements, themes, and
theories) that operate beneath the level of theme-content and subjective
awareness and invention.
And Foucault makes statement tat these rules are ‘the fundamental
codes of a culture- those determine its language, its schemes of
perception, its exchanges, its techniques, its values, the hierarchy of
practices.’ Hence Foucault sees the concept of archaeology as being
central to his newer approach of historical inquiry.
The second important technical term that we should examine is that of
genealogy. Once gain Foucault is not using this term in its ordinary
sense. He is drawing on the work of Nietzsche such as Genealogy of
Morals to fashion a string analytical tool. He counterposes genealogy to
the traditional methods of historical investigation. As he says, its
objective is to ‘record the singularity of events outside any monotonous
finality.’
Genealogy repudiates mutable essences, fixed underlying laws,
metaphysical conclusions; it is interested in identifying
discontinuities instead of unbroken development. While traditional
historians harp on progress and gravity, genealogists focus on
repetitions and play. As Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow in their book
on Foucault’s work – in my judgment the most insightful introduction to
his writings – assert, ‘genealogy’s coat of arms might read: oppose
depth, finality, and interiority. Its banner: mistrust identities in
history; they are only masks, appeals to unity. The deepest truth that
the genealogist has to reveal is ‘the secret that things have no essence
or that their essence was fabricated in a piecemeal fashion from alien
forms.’
Goals
It is clear that genealogy is not particularly enamoured of goals,
schemes, ends in history which are all premised upon a clear purpose put
in place by God or Spirit or Reason. Consequently, it turns its back on
ideas of progress and universal history. Genealogists do not perceive of
history as a progressive march towards freedom with the aid of reason,
but rather an eclectic succession of diverse social formations shaped by
power. As Foucault said, ‘humanity does not gradually progress from
combat to combat until it arrives at universal reciprocity, where the
rule of law finally replaces warfare; humanity installs each of its
violence in a system of rules and this proceeds from domination to
domination.’
An important function performed by genealogy, it seems to me, is to
de-familiarize the familiar – to see the strangeness in what we take to
be normal and ordinary, to challenge conventional responses and turn
them into questions, to convert past into a unfamiliar country with
surprises and diversities. It is Foucault’s way of challenging mainline
continuous history and investing the silenced with voices and the
invisible with eye-catching powers. Consequently, in Foucault’s
histories the marginalized, silenced, those condemned to invisibility
and a state of non-being are made into objects of inquiry.
This is Foucault’s understanding of effective history. As the
distinguished historian Harry Harootunian says effective history
de-familiarizes the familiar in order to show how the past not only
differs from the present, but also refuses to offer the present its
sanctions and resists assimilation to its own requirements.’ Moreover,
effective history is a practice that begins and ends with the present.
And interestingly, Foucault’s aim has always been to write a history of
the present.
Concepts
I have discussed briefly the two concepts archaeology and genealogy
that Foucault disseminated. In his later writings he gave up the idea of
archaeology, which he regarded as too restrictive and did not take
adequately into considerations politics and power, in favor of the idea
of genealogy. Some commentators argue that he totally rejected the
concept of archeology when he embraced genealogy. I think this is an
overstatement. I myself prefer to read them as a pair of complementary
concepts.
As I stated earlier, the idea of power – the distinctive inflection
he gives it – is pivotal to Foucault’s formulations. He saw power not as
a substance but a relation and as a consequence he maintained that power
is not possessed but exercised. What this means is that it is important
that we give up on the idea of power the property of any one whether it
is a king or executive or the State; power signifies the complicated
relations that exist among various segments of society.
Therefore, power has to be understood as a moving situation, whether
individual institutional or social. As a consequence of the fact that
power in conceptualised by Foucault in relational terms, he
characterises political struggles not in terms of total power but in
terms of what he calls relations of power. Contrary to standard opinion,
he rejects the notion that power flows from dominating to dominated, and
makes a case for power as fluid and embedded in social relations in
general. In his writings Foucault makes the point that power is not
solely negative; it can be positive as well as creating the space for
action and choice and the re-focusing on the idea of freedom.
Relevance
These concepts of Foucault that he has put into circulation in his
commentaries on history have a deep relevance to understanding literary
discourse. I would like to refer to one other concept of his, namely,
subjugated knowledge. Throughout his life Foucault distinguished himself
as a transgressive thinker, and therefore it is hardly surprising that
he chose to call attention to this concept. By subjugated knowledge he
primarily meant two things.
First it is the kind of knowledge that has been buried or ignored by
the generality of historians; second, it refers to the kind of knowledge
that in Foucault’s words,’ has been disqualified as non-conceptual
knowledges, as insufficiently elaborated knowledges; naďve knowledges,
hierarchically inferior knowledges, knowledges that are below the
required level of erudition or scientificity.’ This idea of subjugated
knowledges, I am persuaded, has a great bearing on literary creation.
So far I have been laboring to explore the nature and significance of
Michel Foucault as a historian by highlighting some of the central
concepts that underwrite his work. He is, in my estimation, an
innovative thinker who opened up fascinating new paths of inquiry for
historians. However, not all are enthusiastic about his work or
convinced by his intellectual agenda. They complain that he is
anti-historical, ahistorical, too structural, nihilistic and vague; it
is also argued that in his historical excavations he has got his facts
wrong and missed out on important areas of data. In addition, there are
those who criticize him for his elusive and elliptical style which leads
to obscurity. Some of these charges, I dare say, have some merit. As
Foucault himself once remarked,’ No one is perfect’. However, despite
his shortcomings and blind spots, it is my contention that Foucault is a
thinker of the first rank who has galvanized the study and writing of
history.
Literature
It is against this general background that I now wish to turn my
attention to literature, modern Sinhala literature in particular, and
try to see what possible connections can be made with Foucault’s
pathways of thought. Our discussion so far establishes the fact that
Foucault saw history, culture and power as defining each other. This, it
seems to me has great implications for literature. For example, if we
take Gunadasa Amarsekera’s eight novels beginning with Gamanaka Mula
that aim to explore the social history of the past eight decades, one
can make use of this Foucauldian framework with great profit.
In addition Foucault’s work should encourage us to re-examine the
social, political, historical contexts and consequences of literary
production from newer angles of perception. Not only the writing and
reading f literary texts but also the ways in which they circulate and
are subject to categorisation and taught at various levels become
important aspects of cultural work. And Foucault has much to tell us on
this matter.
Similarly, Foucault enables us to think through the role of discourse
in cultural formation in interesting ways. What he has taught us is
that, as the above discussion indicated, cultural change can be most
profitably explained as a function of discourse. Let us, for example,
consider the rise of the Sinhala novel in the early twentieth century as
a consequence of the work of novelists such as Isaac de Silva, Albert de
Silva, A Simon de Silva, M.C,F..Perera and Piyadasa Sirisena. The
discourse that led to the origins of the Sinhala novels consisted of
many phenomena: the rise of secularism, the resistance to colonialism,
the gathering force of nationalism, engagement with modernity, the
emergence of individuality, the concept of Western-inspired romantic
live, the growth of the middle class etc. The intersections of these
diverse constituent elements can be profitably studied using a framework
inspired by Michel Foucault’s work and thereby open up new pathways of
inquiry into the Sinhala novel and the larger cultural discourse.
(To be continued)
|