Of Grammatology and cardinal logic
In the last column in the series exploring the profound ideas that
led to the birth of Reconstruction we said; “ What is obvious is the
myriad of voice present in Of Grammatology and Derrida’s profound
philosophy of deconstruction. Derrida commences Of Grammatology with
three exergeses as ; “ The one who will shine in the science of writing
will shine like the sun. A scribe (EP, p. 87)
“O Samas (sun-god), by your light you scan the totality of lands as
if they were cuneiform signs (ibid.) .
“These three ways of writing correspond almost exactly to three
different stages according to which one can consider men gathered into a
nation. The depicting of objects is appropriate to a savage people;
signs of words and of propositions, to a barbaric people; and the
alphabet to civilised people. J.-J. Rousseau, Essai sur l’origine des
langues.
“Alphabetic script is in itself and for itself the most intelligent.
Hegel, Enzyklopädie ”
What is obvious is that Derrida with these three exergeses, logically
builds up the matrix of his seminal arguments which is, subsequently
developed into what we know today as the philosophy of deconstruction, a
potent theoretical arsenal against Structuralism.”
 |
Jacques Derrida |
Derrida uses the triple exergeses as a launching pad or as a basis to
build his logic of the themes as ; “ This triple exergeses is intended
not only to focus attention on the ethnocentrism which, everywhere and
always, had controlled the concept of writ-ing.
Logocentrism
Nor merely to focus attention on what I shall call logocentrism: the
metaphysics of phonetic writing (for example, of the alphabet) which was
fundamentally—for enigmatic yet essential reasons that are inaccessible
to a simple historical relativism—nothing but the most original and
powerful ethnocentrism, in the process of imposing itself upon the
world, controlling in one and the same order: the concept of writing in
a world where the phoneticisation of writing must dissimulate its own
history as it is produced; the history of (the only) metaphysics, which
has, in spite of all differences, not only from Plato to Hegel (even
including Leibniz) but also, beyond these apparent limits, from the pre-
Socratics to Heidegger, always assigned the origin of truth in general
to the logos: the history of truth, of the truth of truth, has always
been—except for a metaphysical diversion that we shall have to
explain—the debasement of writing, and its repression outside “full”
speech.
The concept of science or the scientificity of science—what has
always been determined as logic—a concept that has always been a
philosophical concept, even if the practice of science has constantly
challenged its imperialism of the logos, by invoking, for example, from
the beginning and ever increasingly, nonphonetic writing. No doubt this
subversion has always been contained within a system of direct address
[système allocutoire] which gave birth to the project of science and to
the conventions of all nonphonetic characteristics. 1 It could not have
been otherwise. None theless, it is a peculiarity of our epoch that, at
the moment when the phoneticization of writing —the historical origin
and structural possibility of philosophy as of science, the condition of
the epistémè—begins to lay hold on world culture, science, in its
advancements, can no longer be satisfied with it.
This inadequation had always already begun to make its presence felt.
But today something lets it appear as such, allows it a kind of takeover
without our being able to translate this novelty into clear cut notions
of mutation, explicitation, accumulation, revolution, or tradition.
These values belong no doubt to the system whose dislocation is today
presented as such, they describe the styles of an historical movement
which was meaningful—like the concept of history itself—only within a
logocentric epoch.
By alluding to a science of writing reined in by metaphor,
metaphysics, and theology, these exergeses must not only announce that
the science of writing—grammatology shows signs of liberation all over
the world, as a result of decisive efforts.
These efforts are necessarily discreet, dispersed, almost
imperceptible; that is a quality of their meaning and of the milieu
within which they produce their operation. I would like to suggest above
all that, however fecund and necessary the undertaking might be, and
even if, given the most favourable hypothesis, it did overcome all
technical and epistemological obstacles as well as all the theological
and meta-physical impediments that have limited it hitherto, such a
science of writing runs the risk of never being established as such and
with that name.
Of never being able to define the unity of its project or its object.
Of not being able either to write its discourse on method or to describe
the limits of its field. For essential reasons: the unity of all that
allows itself to be attempted today through the most diverse concepts of
science and of writing, is, in principle, more or less covertly yet
always, determined by an historicometaphysical epoch of which we merely
glimpse the closure. I do not say the end.
The idea of science and the idea of writing—therefore also of the
science of writing—is meaningful for us only in terms of an origin and
within a world to which a certain concept of the sign (later I shall
call it the concept of sign) and a certain concept of the relationships
between speech and writing, have already been assigned. A most
determined relationship, in spite of its privilege, its necessity, and
the field of vision that it has controlled for a few millennia,
especially in the West, to the point of being now able to produce its
own dislocation and itself proclaim its limits.” In dissecting the first
chapter of ‘Of Grammatology’, David Potts observes; “ All of Western
intellectual history, from the birth of philosophy (and of alphabetic
writing on, has been a “logocentric epoch”.
“Logocentrism” refers to belief in a “logos,” which can usually be
thought of as reason, although it is not simply mental, being “the
origin of truth in general”. Derrida speaks of “logos” instead of
“reason” in order to capture this notion of a guaranteed correspondence
or connection with reality and also because he wishes the term to cover
the gamut of historical conceptions of reason, from the “pre-Socratic”
to the “post-Hegelian”. Being “the origin of truth” (or “constitutive”
of truth means the logos will usually somehow be constitutive of reality
itself. For example, Derrida’s paradigm of logos is the thought of God,
which contains the [Platonic] ideas from which worldly things are
created. But one way or another, logos is always the principle in virtue
of which the objects of thought are intelligible and by means of which
we may grasp them.”
What Derrida questions the well-established basis of ‘All Western
intellectual history’ which is based on logic or logocentrisim.
|