Strange privilege of sound in idealisation
In the series on ‘Of Grammatology’, this week’s column further
examines the seminal ideas of Derrida.
We concluded the last week’s column citing Potts who points out that
“ the concepts of being, truth, sense, logos, and so forth, cannot be
made good within the logocentric framework. It is the work of
deconstruction to expose the tail-swallowing nature of these concepts
and thereby reveal the bankruptcy of logocentrism. Deconstruction does
not attack the concepts of the logocentric epoch from the vantage point
of a new epoch but from within the logocentric epoch--the only place
from which they can be conceived at all.”
Quoting Hegel, Derrida observes, ‘strange privilege of sound in
idealisation’ “absolute proximity of voice and being, of voice and the
meaning of being, of voice and the ideality of meaning. Hegel
demonstrates very clearly the strange privilege of sound in
idealisation, the production of the concept and the self-presence of the
subject.
This ideal motion, in which through the sound what is as it were the
simple subjectivity, the soul of the material thing expresses itself,
the ear receives also in a theoretical way, just as the eye shape and
colour, thus allowing the interiority of the object to become
interiority itself. The ear, on the contrary, perceives the result of
that interior vibration of material substance without placing itself in
a practical relation towards the objects, a result by means of which it
is no longer the material form [Gestalt] in its repose, but the first,
more ideal activity of the soul itself which is manifested.
What is said of sound in general is a fortiori valid for the phone by
which, by virtue of hearing (understanding)-oneself-speak—an
indissociable system—the subject affects itself and is related to itself
in the element of ideality.”
 |
Jacques Derrida |
Potts observes, “What is needed is a wholly new conception of
language which puts writing first. Rather than signifying signifieds in
a series terminating ultimately in a transcendental signified, written
signifiers according to the new conception signify only other
signifiers, not because of a failure of the signifieds but because there
is no need of them. There is only a perpetual chain or circle of
signifiers, an endless “play of signifying references”, which is never
anchored to anything. “This, strictly speaking, amounts to destroying
the concept of ‘sign’ and its entire logic”. The key concept is
differance (with an “a”), which implies both difference and deferance.
Every signifier is inherently different from what it signifies, and we
should uphold this difference, not seek to erase it in a misguided quest
for presence. By the same token every signifier defers recognition of
what it signifies, and we must embrace this also.”
Exteriority
Derrida describes this as; “To this epoch belongs the difference
between signified and signifier, or at least the strange separation of
their “parallelism,” and the exteriority, however extenuated, of the one
to the other. This appurtenance is organised and hierarchised in a
history. The difference between signified and signifier belongs in a
profound and implicit way to the totality of the great epoch covered by
the history of metaphysics, and in a more explicit and more
systematically articulated way to the narrower epoch of Christian
creationism and infinitism when these appropriate the resources of Greek
conceptuality.
This appurtenance is essential and irreducible; one cannot retain the
convenience or the “scientific truth” of the Stoic and later medieval
opposition between signans and signatum without also bringing with it
all its metaphysicotheological roots. To these roots adheres not only
the distinction between the sensible and the intelligible—already a
great deal—with all that it controls, namely, metaphysics in its
totality. And this distinction is generally accepted as self-evident by
the most careful linguists and semiologists, even by those who believe
that the scientificity of their work begins where metaphysics ends.
Thus, for example, as modem structural thought has clearly realised,
language is a system of signs and linguistics is part and parcel of the
science of signs, or semiotics. The mediaeval definition of
sign—“aliquid stat pro aliquo” has been resurrected and put forward as
still valid and productive. Thus the constitutive mark of any sign in
general and of any linguistic sign in particular is its twofold
character: every linguistic unit is bipartite and involves both aspects
—one sensible and the other intelligible, or in other words, both the
signans “signifier” and the signatum “signified”.
Hidden sentiments
These two constituents of a linguistic sign (and of sign in general)
necessarily suppose and require each other. But to these
metaphysico-theological roots many other hidden sediments cling. The
semiological or, more specifically, linguistic “science” cannot
therefore hold on to the difference between signifier and signified—the
very idea of the sign—without the difference between sensible and
intelligible; certainly, but also not without retaining, more profoundly
and more implicitly, and by the same token the reference to a signified
able to “take place” in its intelligibility, before its “fall,” before
any expulsion into the exteriority of the sensible here below.
As the face of pure intelligibility, ii refers to an absolute logos
to which it is immediately united. This absolute logos was an infinite
creative subjectivity in medieval theology: the intelligible face of the
sign remains turned toward the word and the face of God Of course, it is
not a question of “rejecting” these notions; they are necessary and, at
least at present, nothing is conceivable for us without them. It is a
question at first of demonstrating the systematic and historica.
solidarity of the concepts and gestures of thought that one often
believes can be innocently separated. The sign and divinity have the
same place and time of birth. The age of the sign is essentially
theological. Perhaps it will never end. Its historical closure is,
however, outlined. ”
What Derrida argues is that ‘the age of the sign is essentially
theological’. That means that ‘the sign and the divinity has the same
place and time of birth’ and that the process has not yet been closed.
|