Human Rights, Sri Lanka and the international community
by Prof. G. L. Peiris
The human rights discourse is one of the most striking features of
the political landscape in Sri Lanka today. Voices have been raised
stridently, threatening the government of Sri Lanka with dire
consequences arising from intervention by the international community,
having recourse to methods which could possibly extend to military
action. Indeed, it was suggested by one commentator, in an article
published recently in a Sunday newspaper, that the United Nations should
send troops into Sri Lanka for the purpose of ensuring the protection of
human rights.
There never was a more compelling need than there is today to
penetrate the fog of emotive and deceptive language which characterizes
the continuing debate, to lay bare, in conceptual terms, the hollowness
of the arguments used in support of naked intervention and, most
importantly, to achieve the required threshold of public awareness of
the potential effects of allowing these spurious arguments to prevail.
The advocates of intervention needed an apostle to put forward a
convincing theoretical case to buttress their stand. The most elaborate
effort made in Sri Lanka to accomplish this purpose was that of Dr.
Gareth Evans, former Foreign Minister of Australia and now President of
the International Crisis Group, in his exposition "The Limits of State
Sovereignty: The Responsibility to Protect in the 21st Century", in the
eighth Neelan Tiruchelvem Memorial Lecture delivered at the BMICH in
Colombo on 29th July this year. A critical assessment of the content of
this lecture is useful to understand the nature of the issues involved
and their importance for the national interest of Sri Lanka at this
time.
At the centre of the debate is the role of the international
community. Evans begins with the self-evident premise that each
individual State has the responsibility to protect its own citizens. He
proceeds, quite innocuously, to argue that the international community
should, as appropriate, encourage and assist States to exercise that
responsibility. He contends, again justifiably, that the role of the
international community encompasses several elements - reacting
effectively to situations, preventing situations fraught with danger,
and rebuilding societies which have undergone trauma or catastrophe.
Up to this point, there is no grave cause for concern. Evans declares
that international organizations including the United Nations must
acknowledge the responsibility "to warn, to generate effective
preventive strategies and when necessary, to mobilize effective
reaction". He is comfortable with the proposition that "There will be
situations when prevention fails and reaction becomes necessary".
"Reaction", as he understands it, is defined in the next sentence:
"Reaction does not have to mean military reaction; it can involve
political and diplomatic, economic and legal, pressure, all measures
which can themselves reach across the spectrum from persuasive to
intrusive, and from less to more coercive". Then comes the thin end of
the wedge: Evans proclaims, in stark terms, that while military action
is certainly not the first resort, it is by no means unacceptable in
suitable circumstances. While denying emphatically that the purported
doctrine is "only about military intervention", he has no hesitation in
committing himself explicitly to the position that "Coercive military
action is not excluded as a last resort".
The far-reaching implications of this doctrine are immediately
apparent. The conceptual lever, by means of which the doctrine is sought
to be made palatable, is an insidious transition from the notion of
"right" to that of "responsibility". There is a similar shift that is
foreshadowed from "control" to "responsibility". But these are mere
tactics that rely on deft semantic manoeuvre. The appeal to ideas linked
to protection involves a thinly veiled euphemism; and the inductive
reasoning resorted to is specious.
This approach must not be allowed to deflect attention from the
substance which underpins the veneer. Once the facade is penetrated, the
unvarnished interventionist doctrine is seen in sharp relief. In the
words of Evans himself, "The starting point is that any State has the
primary responsibility to protect the individuals within it. But that is
not the finishing point: where the State fails in that responsibility,
through either incapacity or ill-will, a secondary responsibility to
protect falls on the wider international community". The contours of
this doctrine, its proponents concede unabashedly, extend to the
application of force against sovereign States.
Doctrine
Notwithstanding the facile use of terminology involving "humanitarian
intervention" which is, professedly, "overwhelmingly protective" in
character, the practical effect of the doctrine, it is obvious at a
glance, entails the gravest jeopardy to States which are identified as
targets.
The realization is long overdue in our midst that this doctrine, far
from being a remote or theoretical abstraction, inflicts on the
sovereignty and the territorial integrity of Sri Lanka a distressingly
high degree of vulnerability.
This is not a matter of inference or extrapolation. It receives
direct, and uninhibited, expression by Evans himself: "Should the war
move into the LTTE-controlled areas in the north, it is likely to be
much more fierce than the recent fighting in the east, and the impact on
civilians is almost certain to be devastating. As the war grows more
vicious, it could well spill over into areas outside the north - perhaps
through deliberate attacks on civilians designed to provoke excessive,
and politically damaging, replies from the other side. Such attacks and
the communal tensions they are sure to increase, could well lead to the
further erosion of the remaining elements of the rule of law. All this
makes it hard to argue that Sri Lanka is anything but an 'R2P' (right to
protect) situation".
It is clear, then, that on the basis of speculative anticipation
Evans contrives to present a case for prospective intervention, by
military means if necessary, in our country. There can hardly be a more
urgent reason to evaluate, in an objective and dispassionate spirit, the
foundations of this theory with a view to alerting the public of Sri
Lanka about the perils attendant on cavalier acquiescence in this
doctrine.
There are many dangers inherent in it. The gravest among these,
without question, is the incurably vague and open-ended character of the
suggested principle of intervention. Evans contends that the basis of
the doctrine he expounds is "practical and principled". Demonstrably,
however, the opposite is the case.
Evans concedes what is obvious: that the professed doctrine cannot be
"about the protection of everyone from everything", and that "R2P"
situations have to be narrowly defined". He goes on to state: "What
needs to be understood is that not just one criterion but multiple
criteria must be satisfied if coercive, non-consensual military force is
to be deployed within another country's sovereign territory: it is not
just a matter of saying that if a threshold of seriousness is crossed,
then it's time for the invasion to start".
As far as the persuasive quality of the argument is concerned, this
is the Achilles' heel. Evans proceeds to attempt a definition, in
strikingly general terms, of the factors which would cumulatively
represent a legal and moral justification of compulsory intervention.
Apart from the perceived seriousness of the threat, he enumerates, as
relevant criteria, "the motivation or primary purpose of the proposed
military action; last resort, viz. whether there were reasonably
available peaceful alternatives; the proportionality of the response;
and, not least, the balance of consequences".
Ambit
The question, at bottom, is whether the proposed criteria, applied
separately or in combination, offer a sufficiently firm, stable and
predictable basis for distinguishing between those situations which
warrant mandatory intervention against the will of the State concerned,
and circumstances in which such intervention should rightly be denounced
as gratuitous and unacceptable interference.
An overriding consideration in this regard is that, since the
proposed action is to be taken outside the ambit of the Security of the
United Nations and without invocation of its authority, the aggressors
are themselves the arbiters of the reasonableness of intervention. It is
this combination of incompatible roles that is fundamentally repugnant.
The plea by Evans that the beneficiaries of the doctrine are "not
prospective interveners but those needing support" carries no
conviction. It is scarcely consistent with empirical experience that
altruism and lofty objectives are imputable to prospective interveners.
It is all too probable that the reasoning which seeks to fortify the
doctrine will, for all intents and purposes, be of avail only as a
pretext for self-serving action intended to protect not oppressed
populations but vested interests.
The established international order already contains provision for a
mechanism founded on participatory and equitable values. Consequently,
there is no conceivable lacuna in this regard. The mechanism brought
into being by the Charter of the United Nations consists of the
authority and functions of the Security Council. Evans entertains
reservations regarding the effectiveness of this mechanism on the ground
that the power of veto, at the disposal of the permanent members of the
Security Council, may stultify urgent action when it is required.
According to him, this consideration raises "anxious questions about the
integrity of the whole international security system".
The issue here is whether the transfer of these all-encompassing
powers to a group of self-appointed custodians of the public interest in
international affairs represents any change for the better. It calls for
no great acuity of judgement to realize that any resolve to abandon a
representative system mandated by the Charter of the United Nations,
without identifying a viable substitute which has the potential to
command general acceptance, is an exceedingly hazardous course of
action.
Intervention
Moreover, Evans is mistaken when he contends that the innovation be
recommends "has the pedigree to be described as a broadly accepted
international norm, and one with the potential to evolve further into a
rule of customary international law". He claims that the United Nations
60th Anniversary World Summit in September 2005 and the Summit Outcome
Document signify endorsement of the core of the doctrine. This is not
so. The summit Document extends support to some elements of the
doctrine, but only within the framework of the Charter, and subject to
the overarching role of the Security Council as the repository of
decision making power in respect of enforced intervention. Similarly,
the appeal by Evans to Resolution 1706 of 31st August 2006 on Darfur as
a source of support for his argument is unconvincing.
The very fact that a specific Resolution was considered necessary to
legitimize intervention in a particular case, amounts to evidence of the
absence, rather than the existence, of a general principle warranting
intervention. Exceptio probat regulam. The exception proves the rule.
All this has a direct bearing on the vital interests of Sri Lanka.
Evans, turning his attention specifically to Sri Lanka, begins with an
emphatic disclaimer of familiarity with the complex conditions of our
national situation: "We in Crisis Group have only been here on the
ground for a year, and we are still feeling our way".
In light of this caveat, one would naturally expect to find some
degree of reluctance or constraint in prescribing solutions. But this
spirit of circumspection is singularly lacking.
It is hard to argue, Evans maintains, that Sri Lanka is a typical
"R2P" situation. However, he contends, with remarkable self-assurance:
"It may not be one where large-scale atrocity crimes - Cambodia-style,
Rwanda-style, Srebrenica-style, Kosovo-style - are occurring right now,
or immediately about to occur, but it is certainly a situation which is
capable of deteriorating to that extent. So it is an 'R2P' situation".
The extreme danger of this line of argument can be demonstrated
irrefutably. Evans states: "While more than 4,500 have been killed over
the last 20 months, and both government and LTTE forces have repeatedly
violated international humanitarian law, the recent violence has not
crossed the boundary into mass atrocity or obvious genocide, war crimes,
ethnic cleansing or crimes against humanity. The violence has been
contained just this side of full-scale disaster and
internationally-recognized catastrophe".
Sovereignty
It follows from this reasoning that the crucial issue on which would
depend the reasonableness or otherwise of armed intervention against the
will of a sovereign State, with all the consequences flowing from that
consideration, is the answer to the question: Has this tenuous boundary
been crossed or, in the words of Evans himself, are we "just this side"
of an internationally cognizable calamity? We may well ask: Who will
decide this question which has inestimable implications for the future
of our country? By what yardstick will they be guided? What is the
source of their legal or moral authority to make so momentous a decision
on Sri Lanka's behalf? In the absence of plausible answers to these
questions, the overwhelming majority of Sri Lankans may well be forgiven
for feeling, and confessing to, acute discomfort in respect of the basis
of the purported doctrine.
Evans seeks to support his theory by arguing that "national
sovereignty has to be weighed and balanced in these cases against
individual sovereignty". This is a wholly impractical view. The core of
classical political theory with regard to the Social Compact, developed
in the writings of Locke, Hobbes and Rousseau, is that individuals
surrendered their sovereignty to the nation State to lead orderly lives
in a tranquil environment.
In the pre-existing state of nature, Thomas Hobbes declared in his
celebrated work, 'The Leviathan', human life was "nasty, brutish and
short". Few of us would be enamoured of the prospect of reverting to
this state of things.
The essential question, at the conclusion of this analysis, is the
proper perspective which should inform the relationship between Sri
Lanka and the international community. Any worthwhile relationship,
whether among individuals or nations, must be founded on the bedrock of
mutual esteem, dignity and sincerity. This is, necessarily, a matter of
reciprocity. Nothing is as destructive of the spirit of a wholesome
relationship as any element of duress, coercion or intimidation, direct
or oblique, because it erodes the pivotal attribute of self-worth.
This consideration is accentuated by special factors governing the
current situation in Sri Lanka. One of the most regrettable aspects of
the human rights discourse in the Sri Lankan context is its unbridled
exploitation of human rights issues in pursuit of partisan political
agendas. Foreign governments are exhorted today to withhold development
assistancfe from Sri Lanka in the name of human rights; multilateral
financial institutions are dissuaded, by a variety of methods, from
entering into transactions with the government of Sri Lanka; the country
is threatened with the discontinuation of trade benefits which have been
earned on the basis of meritorious performance. These are developments
without parallel in the contemporary history of Sri Lanka. Against such
a unique backdrop, it is surely necessary for the international
community to exercise the greatest vigilance to ensure that human rights
do not become a tool in a relentless political campaign waged against a
democratic government grappling with terrorism and attempting to serve
its people in challenging circumstances. |